FREE! Click here to Join FunTrivia. Thousands of games, quizzes, and lots more!
Quiz about Quod Erat Demonstrandum
Quiz about Quod Erat Demonstrandum

Quod Erat Demonstrandum Trivia Quiz


This quiz is a mishmash of proofs, interesting theorems, and other mathematical marvels. No calculations are involved.

A multiple-choice quiz by redsoxfan325. Estimated time: 7 mins.
  1. Home
  2. »
  3. Quizzes
  4. »
  5. Science Trivia
  6. »
  7. Math
  8. »
  9. Theorems

Author
redsoxfan325
Time
7 mins
Type
Multiple Choice
Quiz #
296,747
Updated
Dec 03 21
# Qns
10
Difficulty
Tough
Avg Score
5 / 10
Plays
551
Question 1 of 10
1. If by assuming a statement is true for some value n and proving it's true for a base case, you can prove that the statement is true for n+1, then you have successfully proved that the statement is true for all n.

What method of proving a statement is this?
Hint


Question 2 of 10
2. The formula for the area of a circle can be derived in at least two different ways. Which of the following is not one of them? Hint


Question 3 of 10
3. Contrary to what some math-phobes believe, the quadratic equation is quite helpful indeed, showing its face in almost all areas of math and math-related sciences. The formula for solving a quadratic equation can be derived by a method known as _____________. Hint


Question 4 of 10
4. The proof that there are an infinite number of primes is based on which of the following statements? Hint


Question 5 of 10
5. When Euclid published his text, "Elements", he included five postulates. One of those postulates has been disputed and actually led to the study of non-Euclidean geometry. Which one was it? Hint


Question 6 of 10
6. I am going to try to prove that 1 = 0.

Proof
1. Let a = b = 1.
2. Thus a2 = ab
3. Subtract b2 from both sides to get a2-b2 = ab-b2.
4. Factor both sides to get (a+b)(a-b) = b(a-b).
5. Divide by (a-b) to get a+b = b.
6. Subtract b from both sides to get a = 0.
7. Since we set a = 1 at the beginning of the proof, we have proved that 1 = 0.

Obviously 1 ≠ 0, so where did this proof go wrong?
Hint


Question 7 of 10
7. Another one similar to the above question.

We are going to "prove" that the infinite sum ∑2n = -1

Proof
1. Let S = ∑2n
2. Thus S = 1+2+4+8+16+...
3. Therefore 2S = 2+4+8+16+32+...
4. Add 1 to get 2S+1 = 1+2+4+8+16+32+...
5. Thus the equation in Step 4 equals the equation in Step 2: 2S+1 = S
6. Subtract S+1 from both sides of the equation in Step 5 to get S = -1.

Where did I go wrong?
Hint


Question 8 of 10
8. Most people have heard of Fermat's Last Theorem, but fewer people have heard of his Little Theorem. What is it? Hint


Question 9 of 10
9. The Banach-Tarski Paradox is a seemingly ridiculous theorem that states that a solid ball in 3 dimensions can be broken into at least 5 pieces and then put back together to form two identical copies of the original ball. The proof of this statement relies heavily on a particular axiom that was somewhat disputed but is now widely accepted. Which axiom is it? Hint


Question 10 of 10
10. The Continuum Hypothesis was a problem that plagued mathematicians for almost a hundred years until it was finally cracked in 1963 by Paul Cohen. Georg Cantor had proved that the size of the real numbers was greater than the size of the natural numbers but this raised the question: Are there sizes of infinity between those two sizes? The conclusion was somewhat startling. What was it? Hint



(Optional) Create a Free FunTrivia ID to save the points you are about to earn:

arrow Select a User ID:
arrow Choose a Password:
arrow Your Email:




Quiz Answer Key and Fun Facts
1. If by assuming a statement is true for some value n and proving it's true for a base case, you can prove that the statement is true for n+1, then you have successfully proved that the statement is true for all n. What method of proving a statement is this?

Answer: proof by induction

For instance, you want to verify that the sum of all numbers from 1 to n is (1/2)(n)(n+1). To do this you would need to verify that (1/2)(n)(n+1) + (n+1) = (1/2)(n+1)((n+1)+1). Distributing yields n²/2+n/2+n+1 = n²/2+3n/2+1. Multiplying both sides by two and combining like terms yields n²+3n+1=n²+3n+1, so the equation is true for all n.

For the incorrect choices:

Proof by contradiction is a proof where you start out by assuming the opposite of what you want to prove and then showing that that assumption leads to a ridiculous conclusion, and thus must be false.

Proof by contrapositive involves proving a different, yet equivalent statement. If you have a logical statement "If P, then Q", then its contrapositive is "If not Q, then not P". If one is true, then they both are. So if you are trying to prove a statement, you can opt instead to prove its contrapositive.

Proof by cases involves breaking up the problem into a finite number of cases which you can tackle individually. This is how the famous Four-Color Theorem was finally solved. Each map was put into one of several categories and then a computer was used to check that each category worked. Not all mathematicians were happy that it was proved this way, but almost all if not every mathematician trusts the result.
2. The formula for the area of a circle can be derived in at least two different ways. Which of the following is not one of them?

Answer: Derivating the function for a sphere of the same radius and evaluating it at the point r=0.

The integration method is best performed in Polar coordinates. ∫∫dA is the integral, where dA = r*drdθ. The bounds on r are [0,R] and the bounds on θ are [0,2π]. Performing the first step of the integral leaves you (1/2)∫R²*dθ. Evaluating this leaves A=πR².

The second method involves breaking up the circle into tiny sectors, with each sector's area approximately equal to r²sin(θ/2)cos(θ/2)=r²sin(θ)/2 (through the double angle identity) where r is the radius of the circle and θ is the central angle of the sector. If each sector has an angle θ, then the whole circle will contain a total of 2π/θ sectors. So the area will equal lim(2π/θ*r²sin(θ)/2) as θ→∞. Canceling the 2's and applying the limit product rule leaves you lim(πr²)*lim(sin(θ)/θ) as θ→∞. Since lim(sin(θ)/θ)=1, the limit evaluates to πr².

The third statement is just math gibberish.
3. Contrary to what some math-phobes believe, the quadratic equation is quite helpful indeed, showing its face in almost all areas of math and math-related sciences. The formula for solving a quadratic equation can be derived by a method known as _____________.

Answer: Completing the Square

Completing the square:

1. ax²+bx+c = 0
2. x²+(b/a)x+(c/a) = 0
3. x²+(b/a)x = -c/a
4. x²+(b/a)x+b²/(4a²) = -c/a+b²/(4a²)
5. [x+b/(2a)]² = b²/(4a²)-4ac/(4a²)
6. [x+b/(2a)]² = (b²-4ac)/(4a²)
7. x+b/(2a) = ±√(b²-4ac)/(2a)
8. x = -b/(2a)±√(b²-4ac)/(2a)
9. x = [-b±√(b²-4ac)]/(2a)

"Negative b plus or minus the square root of b squared minus four a c all over two a."

The other choices:

Integration by parts is used to simplify a complicated integral into a simpler one.

Gaussian Elimination is used to simplify a matrix into reduced row echelon form.

Newton's method uses derivatives to find approximate answers to complicated equations.
4. The proof that there are an infinite number of primes is based on which of the following statements?

Answer: If you assume there are finitely many primes, you can use that finite list of primes to find another prime.

If you have a set of all the primes (2,3,5,...,p) you can always find another prime by looking at the number you get when you multiply your finite list of primes and add one. Since dividing this number by any of the primes in your supposed complete list will always leave a remainder of 1, than this new number is either prime or prime factorable into two or more primes not on your list. Thus, give a finite set of primes, you can always find another one, so there are infinitely many primes.

A Mersenne prime is a prime number of the form 2ⁿ-1, but a number of that form is not necessarily prime (e.g. n=4). Prize money is awarded to people who can find primes over 10 million digits long. The largest known prime (when this quiz was made) is 2⁴³¹¹²⁶⁰⁹ - 1 and contains 12,978,189 digits. (It's a Mersenne prime.) Think you can find the next one?* Get to it!










* You won't.
5. When Euclid published his text, "Elements", he included five postulates. One of those postulates has been disputed and actually led to the study of non-Euclidean geometry. Which one was it?

Answer: the parallel postulate

Euclid's five postulate's were (generally speaking):

1. A line can be created by connecting two points.
2. Lines can be extended indefinitely.
3. A circle can be formed from a point [i.e. center] and a radius.
4. All right angles are congruent.
5. If a line segment intersects two straight lines forming two interior angles on the same side that sum to less than two right angles [i.e. less than 180°], then the two lines intersect at some point.

Euclid could not prove this statement, but reasoned that it had to be true, so he left it as a postulate. Many mathematicians have attempted to prove this over the years, mainly because it is complex compared to the other four, which are very basic. It has not been proved, but a proof has been written proving that it cannot be proved one way or another. Two branches of geometry (hyperbolic and elliptical), both under the shell of non-Euclidean geometry were created, and Einstein actually discovered that when talking about very large spaces (like the universe), Euclidean geometry does not hold and in fact it is hyperbolic geometry that is more applicable. Cool, huh?
6. I am going to try to prove that 1 = 0. Proof 1. Let a = b = 1. 2. Thus a2 = ab 3. Subtract b2 from both sides to get a2-b2 = ab-b2. 4. Factor both sides to get (a+b)(a-b) = b(a-b). 5. Divide by (a-b) to get a+b = b. 6. Subtract b from both sides to get a = 0. 7. Since we set a = 1 at the beginning of the proof, we have proved that 1 = 0. Obviously 1 ≠ 0, so where did this proof go wrong?

Answer: Step 5

The error in step 5 is that when dividing by a-b, we are really dividing by 0, because we set a = b = 1 at the beginning of the proof. Other than that one step though, all the other reasoning is sound.

It's a good thing that 0 ≠ 1 though, or we could prove anything we wanted to.

Try showing this "proof" to people and see if they can catch the error.
7. Another one similar to the above question. We are going to "prove" that the infinite sum ∑2n = -1 Proof 1. Let S = ∑2n 2. Thus S = 1+2+4+8+16+... 3. Therefore 2S = 2+4+8+16+32+... 4. Add 1 to get 2S+1 = 1+2+4+8+16+32+... 5. Thus the equation in Step 4 equals the equation in Step 2: 2S+1 = S 6. Subtract S+1 from both sides of the equation in Step 5 to get S = -1. Where did I go wrong?

Answer: Step 6

The problem occurs in Step 6 because by subtracting S+1, I am subtracting infinity from infinity, which is a mathematical no-no. Up until that point, though, the proof is okay. 2S+1 = S is a perfectly valid equation. If you treat infinity as a number (it's okay here), then 2S+1 becomes 2*infinity+1 = infinity, so 2S+1 does in fact equal S. If this proof were correct, we would have such a ridiculous result. Imagine adding up an infinite string of positive integers and getting something negative!
8. Most people have heard of Fermat's Last Theorem, but fewer people have heard of his Little Theorem. What is it?

Answer: If p is prime then, for any integer a, ap = a (mod p).

This theorem is the motor behind the Fermat Primality Test. The Fermat Primality Test can say for certain that a number is not prime, but can only give a probability that something is prime. Say you want to see whether 319 is prime. Pick an a less than 319, say 101. So a=101 and p=319. 101^319 ≡ 182 (mod 319), so we can conclude that 319 is not prime (because our result was 182 and it should have been 101). It turns out that 11*29 = 319. Now let's test to see whether 317 is prime. We'll use 101 again. 101^317 ≡ 101 (mod 317). So far so good. Let's try another value for a, such as a = 251. 251^317 ≡ 251 (mod 317). Let's check one more, say a = 299. 299^317 ≡ 299 (mod 317). So we can conclude that 317 is probably prime, because Fermat's Test worked for three random, unrelated integers. It turns out that 317 is prime. However, it could have been the case that I was just lucky with my selections. There are times when a^p ≡ a (mod p) holds even when p is not prime. An example of this (from Wikipedia) is p=221 and a=38. The above equation is true even though 221 is composite. (It's 13*17.)

Note that if a is larger than p, you will have to take into account the fact that there exists b such that a ≡ b (mod p) and 0 ≤ b ≤ p. For instance, take p=2 and a=3. 3^2 ≡ 1 (mod 2). This may raise a red flag, but remember that 3 ≡ 1 (mod 2), so by the transitive property, 3^2 ≡ 1 ≡ 3 (mod 2).

For the other choices:

"If x, y, z, and n are natural numbers, there are no x, y, z such that x^n+y^n=z^n for n≥3." - This is Fermat's Last Theorem.

"If n≥2 and (n-1)! ≡ -1 (mod n), then n is prime." - This is Wilson's Theorem.

"If a and p are relatively prime, then a mod p ≠ 0." - This is a true statement though it's nothing earth-shattering.
9. The Banach-Tarski Paradox is a seemingly ridiculous theorem that states that a solid ball in 3 dimensions can be broken into at least 5 pieces and then put back together to form two identical copies of the original ball. The proof of this statement relies heavily on a particular axiom that was somewhat disputed but is now widely accepted. Which axiom is it?

Answer: Axiom of Choice

The Axiom of Choice (AoC) states that if you have a collection of sets (finite or infinite), it is possible to choose exactly one element from each set. Sounds reasonable, doesn't it? Well, if you assume it to be true, you can prove with absolute mathematical certainty the paradox stated in the question. Banach and Tarksi actually proved this theorem to try to contradict the AoC, but it turns out that by using the AoC to create the 5 or mores pieces, you are creating nonmeasurable sets, and thus the idea of volume doesn't really make sense, thereby eliminating any sort of logical contradiction. Most mathematicians accept the AoC because not only is it crucial in a number of important theories, but it also makes life easier in general for mathematicians trying to prove new theorems.

The other choices:

The Axiom of Infinity states that there exists at least one infinite set - the natural numbers.

The Axiom of Separation essentially states that subsets exists and are themselves sets.

The Axiom of Empty Set states that there exists a set with no elements - the empty set.
10. The Continuum Hypothesis was a problem that plagued mathematicians for almost a hundred years until it was finally cracked in 1963 by Paul Cohen. Georg Cantor had proved that the size of the real numbers was greater than the size of the natural numbers but this raised the question: Are there sizes of infinity between those two sizes? The conclusion was somewhat startling. What was it?

Answer: The hypothesis can neither be proved or disproved.

This was an incredibly startling conclusion. In 1931, Kurt Gödel proved the Incompleteness Theorem that implies (in a nutshell) that given any set of axioms, there are statements that can be neither proved nor disproved; however, until 1963, there had been no instances of this theorem appearing anywhere in math. The actual proofs of these theorems are difficult and therefore I won't attempt to go into them on this quiz.

I hope you enjoyed playing this quiz as much as I enjoyed writing it.
Source: Author redsoxfan325

This quiz was reviewed by FunTrivia editor crisw before going online.
Any errors found in FunTrivia content are routinely corrected through our feedback system.
Related Quizzes
1. Benford's Law Average
2. Pythagorean Theorem Average
3. Fermat's Last Theorem Average
4. Basic Math by the Definition Average
5. The Square Root of the Problem Average
6. Pythagoras's Crazy Theorem Average
7. Famous Theorems in Math #1 Difficult
8. All About Math Average
9. Sorry, Wrong Number Easier
10. The Mansion Average
11. Interesting Numbers Average
12. Maths is Useless Tough

12/21/2024, Copyright 2024 FunTrivia, Inc. - Report an Error / Contact Us